Culture Wars/Current Controversies

The Revolutionary Conservative Critique of Oswald Spengler

By Lucian Tudor
Oswald Spengler is by now well-known as one of the major thinkers of the German Conservative
Revolution of the early 20th Century. In fact, he is frequently cited as having been one of the
most determining intellectual influences on German Conservatism of the interwar period – along
with Arthur Moeller van den Bruck and Ernst Jünger – to the point where his cultural pessimist
philosophy is seen to be representative of Revolutionary Conservative views in general (although
in reality most Revolutionary Conservatives held more optimistic views).[1]
To begin our discussion, we shall provide a brief overview of the major themes of Oswald
Spengler‟s philosophy.[2] According to Spengler, every High Culture has its own “soul” (this
refers to the essential character of a Culture) and goes through predictable cycles of birth,
growth, fulfillment, decline, and demise which resemble that of the life of a plant. To quote
Spengler:
A Culture is born in the moment when a great soul awakens out of the proto-spirituality
of ever-childish humanity, and detaches itself, a form from the formless, a bounded and
mortal thing from the boundless and enduring. It blooms on the soil of an
exactly-definable landscape, to which plant-wise it remains bound. It dies when the soul
has actualized the full sum of its possibilities in the shape of peoples, languages, dogmas,
arts, states, sciences, and reverts into the proto-soul.[3]
There is an important distinction in this theory between Kultur (“Culture”) and Zivilisation
(“Civilization”). Kultur refers to the beginning phase of a High Culture which is marked by rural
life, religiosity, vitality, will-to-power, and ascendant instincts, while Zivilisation refers to the
later phase which is marked by urbanization, irreligion, purely rational intellect, mechanized life,
and decadence. Although he acknowledged other High Cultures, Spengler focused particularly
on three High Cultures which he distinguished and made comparisons between: the Magian, the
Classical (Greco-Roman), and the present Western High Culture. He held the view that the West,
which was in its later Zivilisation phase, would soon enter a final imperialistic and “Caesarist”
stage – a stage which, according to Spengler, marks the final flash before the end of a High
Culture.[4]
Perhaps Spengler‟s most important contribution to the Conservative Revolution, however, was
his theory of “Prussian Socialism,” which formed the basis of his view that conservatives and
socialists should unite. In his work he argued that the Prussian character, which was the German
character par excellence, was essentially socialist. For Spengler, true socialism was primarily a
matter of ethics rather than economics. This ethical, Prussian socialism meant the development
and practice of work ethic, discipline, obedience, a sense of duty to the greater good and the
state, self-sacrifice, and the possibility of attaining any rank by talent. Prussian socialism was
differentiated from Marxism and liberalism. Marxism was not true socialism because it was
materialistic and based on class conflict, which stood in contrast with the Prussian ethics of the
state. Also in contrast to Prussian socialism was liberalism and capitalism, which negated the
idea of duty, practiced a “piracy principle,” and created the rule of money.[5]
Oswald Spengler‟s theories of predictable culture cycles, of the separation between Kultur and
Zivilisation, of the Western High Culture as being in a state of decline, and of a non-Marxist
form of socialism, have all received a great deal of attention in early 20th Century Germany, and
there is no doubt that they had influenced Right-wing thought at the time. However, it is often
forgotten just how divergent the views of many Revolutionary Conservatives were from
Spengler‟s, even if they did study and draw from his theories, just as an overemphasis on
Spenglerian theory in the Conservative Revolution has led many scholars to overlook the variety
of other important influences on the German Right. Ironically, those who were influenced the
most by Spengler – not only the German Revolutionary Conservatives, but also later the
Traditionalists and the New Rightists – have mixed appreciation with critique. It is this reality
which needs to be emphasized: the majority of Conservative intellectuals who have appreciated
Spengler have simultaneously delivered the very significant message that Spengler‟s philosophy
needs to be viewed critically, and that as a whole it is not acceptable.
The most important critique of Spengler among the Revolutionary Conservative intellectuals was
that made by Arthur Moeller van den Bruck.[6] Moeller agreed with certain basic ideas in
Spengler‟s work, including the division between Kultur and Zivilisation, with the idea of the
decline of the Western Culture, and with his concept of socialism, which Moeller had already
expressed in an earlier and somewhat different form in Der Preussische Stil (“The Prussian
Style,” 1916).[7] However, Moeller resolutely rejected Spengler‟s deterministic and fatalistic
view of history, as well as the notion of destined culture cycles. Moeller asserted that history was
essentially unpredictable and unfixed: “There is always a beginning (…) History is the story of
that which is not calculated.”[8] Furthermore, he argued that history should not be seen as a
“circle” (in Spengler‟s manner) but rather a “spiral,” and a nation in decline could actually
reverse its decline if certain psychological changes and events could take place within it.[9]
The most radical contradiction with Spengler made by Moeller van den Bruck was the rejection
of Spengler‟s cultural morphology, since Moeller believed that Germany could not even be
classified as part of the “West,” but rather that it represented a distinct culture in its own right,
one which even had more in common in spirit with Russia than with the “West,” and which was
destined to rise while France and England fell.[10] However, we must note here that the notion
that Germany is non-Western was not unique to Moeller, for Werner Sombart, Edgar Julius Jung,
and Othmar Spann have all argued that Germans belonged to a very different cultural type from
that of the Western nations, especially from the culture of the Anglo-Saxon world. For these
authors, Germany represented a culture which was more oriented towards community,
spirituality, and heroism, while the modern “West” was more oriented towards individualism,
materialism, and capitalistic ethics. They further argued that any presence of Western
characteristics in modern Germany was due to a recent poisoning of German culture by the West
which the German people had a duty to overcome through sociocultural revolution.[11]
Another key intellectual of the German Conservative Revolution, Hans Freyer, also presented a
critical analysis of Spenglerian philosophy.[12] Due to his view that that there is no certain and
determined progress in history, Freyer agreed with Spengler‟s rejection of the linear view of
progress. Freyer‟s philosophy of culture also emphasized cultural particularism and the disparity
between peoples and cultures, which was why he agreed with Spengler in terms of the basic
conception of cultures possessing a vital center and with the idea of each culture marking a
particular kind of human being. Being a proponent of a community-oriented state socialism,
Freyer found Spengler‟s anti-individualist “Prussian socialism” to be agreeable. Throughout his
works, Freyer had also discussed many of the same themes as Spengler – including the
integrative function of war, hierarchies in society, the challenges of technological developments,
cultural form and unity – but in a distinct manner oriented towards social theory.[13]
However, Freyer argued that the idea of historical (cultural) types and that cultures were the
product of an essence which grew over time were already expressed in different forms long
before Spengler in the works of Karl Lamprecht, Wilhelm Dilthey, and Hegel. It is also
noteworthy that Freyer‟s own sociology of cultural categories differed from Spengler‟s
morphology. In his earlier works, Freyer focused primarily on the nature of the cultures of
particular peoples (Völker) rather than the broad High Cultures, whereas in his later works he
stressed the interrelatedness of all the various European cultures across the millennia. Rejecting
Spengler‟s notion of cultures as being incommensurable, Freyer‟s “history regarded modern
Europe as composed of „layers‟ of culture from the past, and Freyer was at pains to show that
major historical cultures had grown by drawing upon the legacy of past cultures.”[14] Finally,
rejecting Spengler‟s historical determinism, Freyer had “warned his readers not to be ensnared
by the powerful organic metaphors of the book [Der Untergang des Abendlandes] … The
demands of the present and of the future could not be „deduced‟ from insights into the patterns of
culture … but were ultimately based on „the wager of action‟ (das Wagnis der Tat).”[15]
Yet another important Conservative critique of Spengler was made by the Italian Perennial
Traditionalist philosopher Julius Evola, who was himself influenced by the Conservative
Revolution but developed a very distinct line of thought. In his The Path of Cinnabar, Evola
showed appreciation for Spengler‟s philosophy, particularly in regards to the criticism of the
modern rationalist and mechanized Zivilisation of the “West” and with the complete rejection of
the idea of progress.[16] Some scholars, such as H.T. Hansen, stress the influence of Spengler‟s
thought on Evola‟s thought, but it is important to remember that Evola‟s cultural views differed
significantly from Spengler‟s due to Evola‟s focus on what he viewed as the shifting role of a
metaphysical Perennial Tradition across history as opposed to historically determined
cultures.[17]
In his critique, Evola pointed out that one of the major flaws in Spengler‟s thought was that he
“lacked any understanding of metaphysics and transcendence, which embody the essence of each
genuine Kultur.”[18] Spengler could analyze the nature of Zivilisation very well, but his
irreligious views caused him to have little understanding of the higher spiritual forces which
deeply affected human life and the nature of cultures, without which one cannot clearly grasp the
defining characteristic of Kultur. As Robert Steuckers has pointed out, Evola also found
Spengler‟s analysis of Classical and Eastern cultures to be very flawed, particularly as a result of
the “irrationalist” philosophical influences on Spengler: “Evola thinks this vitalism leads
Spengler to say „things that make one blush‟ about Buddhism, Taoism, Stoicism, and
Greco-Roman civilization (which, for Spengler, is merely a civilization of „corporeity‟).”[19]
Also problematic for Evola was “Spengler‟s valorization of „Faustian man,‟ a figure born in the
Age of Discovery, the Renaissance and humanism; by this temporal determination, Faustian man
is carried towards horizontality rather than towards verticality.”[20]
Finally, we must make a note of the more recent reception of Spenglerian philosophy in the
European New Right and Identitarianism: Oswald Spengler‟s works have been studied and
critiqued by nearly all major New Right and Identitarian intellectuals, including especially Alain
de Benoist, Dominique Venner, Pierre Krebs, Guillaume Faye, Julien Freund, and Tomislav
Sunic. The New Right view of Spenglerian theory is unique, but is also very much reminiscent of
Revolutionary Conservative critiques of Moeller van den Bruck and Hans Freyer. Like Spengler
and many other thinkers, New Right intellectuals also critique the “ideology of progress,”
although it is significant that, unlike Spengler, they do not do this to accept a notion of rigid
cycles in history nor to reject the existence of any progress. Rather, the New Right critique aims
to repudiate the unbalanced notion of linear and inevitable progress which depreciates all past
culture in favor of the present, while still recognizing that some positive progress does exist,
which it advocates reconciling with traditional culture to achieve a more balanced cultural
order.[21] Furthermore, addressing Spengler‟s historical determinism, Alain de Benoist has
written that “from Eduard Spranger to Theodor W. Adorno, the principal reproach directed at
Spengler evidently refers to his „fatalism‟ and to his „determinism.‟ The question is to know up
to what point man is prisoner of his own history. Up to what point can one no longer change his
course?”[22]
Like their Revolutionary Conservative precursors, New Rightists reject any fatalist and
determinist notion of history, and do not believe that any people is doomed to inevitable decline;
“Decadence is therefore not an inescapable phenomenon, as Spengler wrongly thought,” wrote
Pierre Krebs, echoing the thoughts of other authors.[23] While the New Rightists accept
Spengler‟s idea of Western decline, they have posed Europe and the West as two antagonistic
entities. According to this new cultural philosophy, the genuine European culture is represented
by numerous traditions rooted in the most ancient European cultures, and must be posed as
incompatible with the modern “West,” which is the cultural emanation of early modern
liberalism, egalitarianism, and individualism.
The New Right may agree with Spengler that the “West” is undergoing decline, “but this original
pessimism does not overshadow the purpose of the New Right: The West has encountered the
ultimate phase of decadence, consequently we must definitively break with the Western
civilization and recover the memory of a Europe liberated from the egalitarianisms…”[24] Thus,
from the Identitarian perspective, the “West” is identified as a globalist and universalist entity
which had harmed the identities of European and non-European peoples alike. In the same way
that Revolutionary Conservatives had called for Germans to assert the rights and identity of their
people in their time period, New Rightists call for the overcoming of the liberal, cosmopolitan
Western Civilization to reassert the more profound cultural and spiritual identity of Europeans,
based on the “regeneration of history” and a reference to their multi-form and multi-millennial
heritage.
Notes
[1] An example of such an assertion regarding cultural pessimism can be seen in “Part III. Three
Major Expressions of Neo-Conservatism” in Klemens von Klemperer, Germany’s New
Conservatism: Its History and Dilemma in the Twentieth Century (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1968).
[2] To supplement our short summary of Spenglerian philosophy, we would like to note that one
the best overviews of Spengler‟s philosophy in English is Stephen M. Borthwick, “Historian of
the Future: An Introduction to Oswald Spengler‟s Life and Works for the Curious Passer-by and
the Interested Student,” Institute for Oswald Spengler Studies, 2011,
<https://sites.google.com/site/spenglerinstitute/Biography&gt;.
[3] Oswald Spengler, The Decline of the West Vol. 1: Form and Actuality (New York: Alfred A.
Knopf, 1926), p. 106.
[4] Ibid.
[5] See “Prussianism and Socialism” in Oswald Spengler, Selected Essays (Chicago:
Gateway/Henry Regnery, 1967).
[6] For a good overview of Moeller‟s thought, see Lucian Tudor, “Arthur Moeller van den
Bruck: The Man & His Thought,” Counter-Currents Publishing, 17 August 2012,
<http://www.counter-currents.com/2012/08/arthur-moeller-van-den-bruck-the-man-and-his-thou
ght/>.
[7] See Fritz Stern, The Politics of Cultural Despair (Berkeley & Los Angeles: University of
California Press, 1974), pp. 238-239, and Alain de Benoist, “Arthur Moeller van den Bruck,”
Elementos: Revista de Metapolítica para una Civilización Europea No. 15 (11 June 2011), p. 30,
40-42. <http://issuu.com/sebastianjlorenz/docs/elementos_n__15&gt;.
[8] Arthur Moeller van den Bruck as quoted in Benoist, “Arthur Moeller van den Bruck,” p. 41.
[9] Ibid., p. 41.
[10] Ibid., pp. 41-43.
[11] See Fritz K. Ringer, The Decline of the German Mandarins: The German Academic
Community, 1890–1933 (Hanover: University Press of New England, 1990), pp. 183 ff.; John J.
Haag, Othmar Spann and the Politics of “Totality”: Corporatism in Theory and Practice (Ph.D.
Thesis, Rice University, 1969), pp. 24-26, 78, 111.; Alexander Jacob‟s introduction and “Part I:
The Intellectual Foundations of Politics” in Edgar Julius Jung, The Rule of the Inferiour, Vol. 1
(Lewiston, New York: Edwin Mellon Press, 1995).
[12] For a brief introduction to Freyer‟s philosophy, see Lucian Tudor, “Hans Freyer: The Quest
for Collective Meaning,” Counter-Currents Publishing, 22 February 2013,
<http://www.counter-currents.com/2013/02/hans-freyer-the-quest-for-collective-meaning/&gt;.
[13] See Jerry Z. Muller, The Other God That Failed: Hans Freyer and the Deradicalization of
German Conservatism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), pp. 78-79, 120-121.
[14] Ibid., p. 335.
[15] Ibid., p. 79.
[16] See Julius Evola, The Path of Cinnabar (London: Integral Tradition Publishing, 2009), pp.
203-204.
[17] See H.T. Hansen, “Julius Evola‟s Political Endeavors,” in Julius Evola, Men Among the
Ruins: Postwar Reflections of a Radical Traditionalist (Rochester: Inner Traditions, 2002), pp.
15-17.
[18] Evola, Path of Cinnabar, p. 204.
[19] Robert Steuckers, “Evola & Spengler”, Counter-Currents Publishing, 20 September 2010,
<http://www.counter-currents.com/2010/09/evola-spengler/&gt; .
[20] Ibid.
[21] In a description that applies as much to the New Right as to the Eurasianists, Alexander
Dugin wrote of a vision in which “the formal opposition between tradition and modernity is
removed… the realities superseded by the period of Enlightenment obtain a legitimate place –
these are religion, ethnos, empire, cult, legend, etc. In the same time, a technological
breakthrough, economical development, social fairness, labour liberation, etc. are taken from the
Modern” (See Alexander Dugin, “Multipolarism as an Open Project,” Journal of Eurasian
Affairs Vol. 1, No. 1 (September 2013), pp. 12-13).
[22] Alain de Benoist, “Oswald Spengler,” Elementos: Revista de Metapolítica para una
Civilización Europea No. 10 (15 April 2011), p.
13.<http://issuu.com/sebastianjlorenz/docs/elementos_n__10&gt;.
[23] Pierre Krebs, Fighting for the Essence (London: Arktos, 2012), p. 34.
[24] Sebastian J. Lorenz, “El Decadentismo Occidental, desde la Konservative Revolution a la
Nouvelle Droite,”Elementos No. 10, p. 5.
—————
Tudor, Lucian. “The Revolutionary Conservative Critique of Oswald Spengler.” Tankesmedjan
Motpol, 7 November 2014.
<http://www.motpol.nu/english/2014/11/07/the-revolutionary-conservative-critique-of-oswald-s
pengler/ >.

Leave a Reply